Thursday 31 December 2020

Conatus Classics 2020

 


Ancient Greek Thinkers

Mythos, Logos, and the Presocratics

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/05/mythos-logos-and-presocratics.html

 

Nomos / Physis

Part 1  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/06/nomos-physis-part-1.html

Part 2  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/06/nomos-physis-part-2.html

 

The Physis of Things

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/06/the-physis-of-things.html


Pherecydes

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/pherecydes-thinking-caveman.html

 

Miletus

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/getting-ionic-at-miletus.html


Thales

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/2-or-3-things-i-know-about-thales.html


Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans

Part 1 : Pythagoras and Philolaus

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/nailing-maths-with-pythagoras.html

Part 2 : Pythagoras and Plato – Encountering Metempsychosis

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/passing-souls-with-pythagoras.html

 

Sophocles : Antigone

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/p/classical-greek-antigone.html


Solon

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/09/solon-law-and-order.html

 

Homer’s People

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/11/homer-peoples-poet.html


Democritus

Part 1  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/12/democritus-part-1.html

Part 2  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/12/democritus-part-2.html


The ‘Greek Dramatists vs. Filmmakers’ Series

Introduction

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/08/greek-dramatists-vs-filmmakers-prelude.html

 

Homer

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/08/homer-first-man-of-literature.html

 

Homer and Aeschylus

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/08/from-time-to-time-homer-x-aeschylus.html

 

Aeschylus and David W. Griffith

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/09/greek-dramatists-vs-filmmakers.html


Sophocles and Akira Kurosawa

Part 1  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/09/greek-dramatists-vs-filmmakers_27.html

Part 2  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/12/sophocles-x-kurosawa-riddle-of-man.html

 

Euripides and Sam Peckinpah

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/12/greek-dramatists-vs-filmmakers.html

 

Thank you very much for your support!

 

by Ed Law

Conatus Classics


Wednesday 30 December 2020

2020以戲服人集合

 


Persona : Bergman, Ibsen, Strindberg

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/02/persona-20-bergman-x-ibsen-x-strindberg.html



冬日之光 Winter Light (director: Ingmar Bergman)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/02/winter-light.html



紅塵百劫 The Color of Pomegranates (director: Sergei Parajanov)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/03/the-color-of-pomegranates.html



銀翼殺手 Blade Runner and Postmodernism (director: Ridley Scott)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/04/blade-runner-and-postmodernism.html



獵鹿者 The Deer Hunter (director: Michael Cimino)

Part 1  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/deer-hunter-part-1.html

Part 2  http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/07/deer-hunter-part-2.html


納粹狂魔 The Damned (director: Luchino Visconti)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/08/damned.html


情懷九月天 September (director: Woody Allen)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/09/september.html


 

豁達的天空 Sling Blade (director: Billy Bob Thornton)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/09/sling-blade.html


綫人 Le Doulos (director: Jean-Pierre Melville)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/10/blog-post.html


天國與地獄 High and Low (director: Akira Kurosawa)

http://emockedlaw.blogspot.com/2020/08/blog-post.html



by Ed Law

以戲服人 Film Analysis


Monday 28 December 2020

Democritus, Part 2



‘Everywhere man blames nature and fate yet his fate is mostly but the echo of 

his character and passion, his mistakes and his weaknesses.’

- Democritus 


Democritus is the natural philosopher par excellence. Through his commitment to atomism, the ancient Greek thinker has provided us a fully naturalistic view regarding humanity. Though some subsequent thinkers might find his ideas dangerous – for Plato that was too materialistic; for Aristotle that was not continuous – classical atomism stood the test of time and it experienced an exciting revival in the Scientific Revolution of the 17th century. A brief digression would be appropriate, because what happened at the later era has found a few parallels with the antiquity.


While the Pre-Socratic philosophers inquired into natural phenomena by giving up mythical explanations and divine intervention, the mechanical philosophers of 17th century interrogated nature by distancing themselves from the Aristotelian-Scholastic philosophy prevalent in medieval Europe. The mechanical philosophers were the practitioners of natural philosophy, and they were often scientifically-minded and placed their trust in empirical methods for the acquisition of knowledge. Philosophers like Gassendi, Hobbes, Descartes, Locke, Boyle and Newton were advocates of corpuscularianism – a theory that proposed corpuscles – groups of particles (rather than individual atoms) as the origin of all things. Like atoms, corpuscles could aggregate to form more complex structures. The resulting properties of the corpuscular structure, as perceived by our senses, would lead to different observable properties we could experience. In particular, John Locke was a philosopher who endorsed corpuscularianism. His epistemology took a lot of influence from this theory, and his idea was indeed very similar to the way how modern Chemistry works. 


In Locke’s epistemology, ‘real essence’ and ‘nominal essence’ was distinguished. The ‘real essence’ of a thing was its corpuscular structure, which corresponded to its primary properties (like the ‘molecular structure’ of Chemistry). In contrast the ‘nominal essence’ of a thing was its properties that resulted from sense perceptions, corresponding to the secondary qualities (like how the chemical compound looked or smelt, for example). So in Locke’s theory the key of acquiring true knowledge was to start from an understanding of the real essence – the structure of corpuscular structure, the arrangement of the particles – and then moved up from the explanation of primary qualities to secondary qualities. The approach was not very different from an extrapolation of microscopic properties to macroscopic qualities commonplace in natural science.


It is important to note that, unlike modern physical sciences, philosophical atomism and corpuscularianism are not empirical per se, because there are no instrumentations that can verify the presence of atoms and particles. Many natural philosophers and scientists from the 17th century have attempted to use different empirical approaches to demonstrate the presence of atoms and corpuscles, yet they were mostly met with failure, either due to epistemological issues (for example, an attempt to extrapolate macroscale observations into micro-/atomic scale observations) or due to poor design of experiments (e.g. primitive microscopy and transport phenomena), resulting in invalid conclusions. It was only in later centuries that a conclusive demonstration of atomic theory for physical science would become possible.


Returning to Democritus. What did the ancient atomist tell us the nature of soul? Though described rather vaguely, Democritus believed humans possessed 2 kinds of atoms: soul atoms and body atoms. One soul atom corresponded with one body atom, and the atoms were all energetic in a sense that they travelled through the human body. Democritus also had other theories regarding various issues from vision to dreams, yet they were rather unbelievable by today’s standard. What is more important is a vision offered by both Leucippus and Democritus – that atoms were governed by necessity. The atomism from these thinkers was deterministic in nature, and it was very unfortunate that they have failed to specify what role chance might play in their worldviews. 


The atomism I have described so far has a few implications for us to bear. Thus, for Democritus there was no Aeschylean cosmic justice, as in ‘The Oresteia’. There was not a notion that the Divine would eventually come to exert justice, just because the time has not yet come. Democritus’ atomist view was distinct, and caused some controversy, because that was not teleological (and that certainly troubled Aristotle in particular). In Democritus’ system that was not a wise and all-knowing spirit to guide us, nor did we have any final purposes for our existence. Atoms were moving through the void, yet they did not know what they were going to and what they would eventually become in the final stage. That made the contentious ideas of atomism even more nihilistic: if reality is all about a bunch of atoms shooting around the universe aimlessly, that what is the point of life? What do we need to guide ourselves to lead a moral and fulfilling existence? How the doctrines of atomism could be correlated to ethical considerations have always been a challenge for the thinkers from the school of atomism. Philosophers from later era, such as Epicurus and Lucretius, have tried very hard to compile a systematic worldview that accounted for the materialistic perspective and its potential moral implications. Democritus also has stated some implications of his metaphysics for ethics, and they were mostly organized as maxims. 


Democritus, through his denial of teleological purposes and cosmic justice, took a more naturalistic view for human lives. In a view not very different from B. F. Skinner, the ancient philosopher believed our actions were the responses that originated from our interactions with the environment, rather than other spiritual factors. The behaviourist view would influence many materialists for the years to come. Democritus also advised his audience that the fear of gods was pointless. When humans did not use reason and observations to understand natural phenomena, like a thunderstorm, they would attribute these mysterious phenomena to superstitious explanations – like ‘Zeus is angry’ or ‘Hera is jealous’, and resulted in an unnecessary fear and worry. Democritus, among other fellow natural philosophers, might not be considered atheists in a strong sense, yet they all encouraged the people to focus on the real reason why the phenomena happened – the scientific reasons.  Future generations of atomist like Epicurus and Lucretius would further elaborate this line of thought in their work.


‘A life without a feast is a long road without an inn.’

-Democritus


Democritus has told us a lot about atoms, yet he also had a real lot to say about ethics. Given the large amounts of ethical statement from him, and the doubt of completeness, it is very difficult to say if he has got a consistent moral philosophy. Nevertheless, by reading many of these thoughts of wisdom, one can easily picture Democritus to be a great personality, with sparks of humor and witticism throughout his writings. While the philosopher might have devoted his life to the study of nature, Democritean ethics were full of humanistic concerns. One should not be surprised by the aim of human life endorsed by the Laughing Philosopher - to have an optimistic outlook and to achieve a peace of mind. For Democritus, happiness for life was not merely about sensual pleasure and material wealth, it was acquired from a spiritual peace and freedom from perturbation of lives. Why not let Democritus speak for himself?


 ‘For joy and absence of joy is the boundary of advantage and disadvantage.’


Democritus maintained that prior to a life of joyfulness, one should exercise reason.


‘Reason is a powerful persuader.’


Democritus believed in education. He believed an opportunity to learn could counteract against misfortune. 


‘Education is an ornament for the fortunate, a refuge for the unfortunate.’


‘The hopes of the educated are stronger than the wealth of the ignorant.’


‘Nature and teaching are similar, for teaching changes a man’s shape 

and nature acts by changing shape.’


Thus he stressed the importance of avoiding bad influences in life.


‘Frequent association with the wicked increases a disposition to vice.’


‘When wealth comes from wicked deeds it makes the disgrace more conspicuous.’


Democritus cherished values like nobility, courage and self-confidence. He felt that these were the very qualities towards a fulfilling existence.


‘Great joys come from contemplating noble deeds.’


‘Courage makes disaster small.’


‘A good man takes no account of the censures of the bad.’


Yet he might have occasional charges of sexism, like many of the ancient thinkers.


‘To be ruled by a woman is the final insult of a man.’


Nevertheless, he thoughtfully advised us not to laugh at other’s misfortunes, lest that one day, that would be our turn to suffer. 


‘Those who take pleasure in the disasters of their neighbors do not understand 

how the affairs of fortune are complex to all, and they lack appropriate delight.’


Finally, a statement strangely suitable for the current situation in our world.


‘Do not suspect everyone – but be cautious and safe.’


(End of Part 2)


Concluding Remarks

Thus we arrive at the end of Conatus Classics 2020. I feel great to have started my first article on the history of thoughts in May, and have the motivation to write a number of articles about Pre-Socratic and Classical Greece, who I have always fascinated with and yet did not have a chance to talk about that in my previous articles. I will keep up the work and continue to share with you the ideas from these great minds who have ever graced human history!


by Ed Law

Conatus Classics


Thank you for your support! 

Conatus Classics will see you again in 2021!


Sunday 27 December 2020

Democritus, Part 1

 


If you are aware of my science blog, or you have ever encountered a gamer by the name of ‘The Laughing Chemist’ online, you may wonder where I got this alias from. The name is actually an inspiration from one of the philosophers I admire the most in the history of thoughts: Democritus of Abdera. Democritus was probably the last of the key Pre-Socratic philosophers, and he could be considered the ultimate natural philosopher of Ancient Greece. The great philosopher was committed to the almost completely materialistic accounts of everything in his world, which was a stance unprecedented until that stage of Greek philosophy. His philosophical outlook was probably the most complete and systematic of all of Pre-Socratic thoughts, from his account of reality to advice of how one should live ethically. To many, Democritus was one of the first natural scientists of humanity. His theory of atoms might have been undermined for many years in the Western culture, yet it experienced a revival in the Scientific Revolution of the 17th century, and that would eventually become the foundations of modern physical science. From his writings one can easily get the impression that Democritus has lived as a very fine human being – his emphasis of a cheerful outlook on life has earned him the name of ‘The Laughing Philosopher’. And you will be even happier if you understand true knowledge!


There are two aspects, due to various reasons, that we are not sure about Democritus. The first aspect is the connection of Democritus to another philosopher, Leucippus. In ancient writings, the two philosophers were often mentioned together and it was alleged that Leucippus was the teacher of Democritus. While there are some sayings which are attributed to Leucippus, we are not certain if he has existed at all in history. Thus, the materialist theory of atomism tends to be associated with the Laughing Philosopher, or they are attributed to both philosophers at the same time.

 

The second aspect is the reception of Democritus in antiquity. While Democritus is considered as a Pre-Socratic philosopher, the notion is actually quite misleading because the designation implies that Democritus lived before Socrates. The truth is, Democritus and Socrates were actually contemporaries and indeed Democritus was younger than Socrates! So it is quite likely that Socrates and Democritus were aware of each other’s ideas, but we did not know if they have interacted with each other at all. The reason is because Socrates never wrote anything – all we know about Socrates’ thinking was from Plato’s work. While in Plato we have read that Socrates has shifted his focus from an interest of natural philosophy to humanism, we did not have any idea of their opinions on Democritus, because Plato did not mention Democritus at all. It was alleged that Plato hated Democritus’ ideas (it could not be proved), and that made sense because Plato would likely perceive Democritus’ materialism to be belonged to the sensual world rather than the world of Forms. It was a puzzling move because even when Plato despised the Sophists as swindlers of knowledge, he still mentioned their teachings and challenged their ideas in a number of his world. So leaving out Democritus was a big mystery. Aristotle, who also disagreed with Democritus for different reasons, was less hostile in this respect and gave the natural philosopher some credits in the development of philosophical thoughts.

 

Democritus, and his mentor Leucippus, were advocates of atomism. The word ‘atom’ should be familiar to anyone in science, yet the meaning for the ancient thinkers were broader – and in a sense less precise – than the demands from scientific rigor. The Greek word for atom is ‘atomos’, which literally means ‘uncuttable’. Literally, an atom for these materialist philosophers was a single particle. The thinkers took the liberty to say that the atoms had different size, shape, and also texture, leading to the different things that human experienced in the universe. The atomists asserted that atoms were not infinitely divisible, meaning that one could not indefinitely divided an atom to a smaller piece. There was a limit to the division, and the limit signified the essence of that thing.

 

The origin of ancient atomism followed a larger trend of the development of Pre-Socratic philosophy: the responses towards the Eleatic school of philosophy. Parmenides of Elea, who was considered as the founder of the Eleatic school of thought, was probably the first who proposed a rational account of reality in Western history. For him, the metaphysical origin was ‘being’, which was unchangeable, static and spherical. The reality Parmenides speculated was very different from the appearances our common senses addressed to us, thus he was considered as the founder of the field of metaphysics, which concerned the reality of things. Parmenides’ appearance-reality distinction would eventually be taken to extreme by later thinkers such as Plato, and his followers have proposed further accounts and questions regarding reality, such as questions of movement and multiplicity. The philosophers after Parmenides – Empedocles, Anaxagoras, Democritus – have all come up with their own solutions to the Eleatic school’s challenges. Denying Parmenides’ assertion there are no void (empty space) in reality, the atomists believed that only atoms and void existed in the world. Democritus was innovative in the sense that he was probably the first thinker to propose and address the importance of void for out world. Moreover, atoms possessed the attributes of movement, and they were in constant motion through the void, and the atoms could collide with each other to generate new things.  It should also be reiterated that a key disagreement between the atomists and the Eleatic thinkers were the indivisibility of things. Thus one can see that the motivation of atomism was not from a desire to discover some novel ‘science’, but actually as a philosophical response to the Eleatic challenge.

 

Democritus’ materialistic account of things was therefore an eliminative atomism. That means only atoms are metaphysically real, and all other appearances are conventions or mere illusions. This standpoint was reminiscent of the nomos-physis distinction of Classical Greek, succinctly summarized by one of his most famous quotes: 

“By convention sweet and by convention bitter, 

by convention hot, by convention cold, by convention color; 

but in reality atoms and void.”

-Democritus 

The distinction between atomic reality and convention would also influence later thinkers. In the 17th century, the natural philosophers stressed the distinction of primary qualities and secondary qualities of things (details in the next article). In short, the primary qualities reflect what the thing really is – its atomic compositions and arrangement, that will not be altered due to perception by sensory organs or other subjective factors. The secondary qualities, in contrast, are originated from sense impressions – the ‘convention’ side of things.


From the understanding of atomic properties, Democritus also proposed the mechanism for the formation of the universe. Because atoms have very different properties, they can be combined in different ways and that can result in formation of different worlds. Democritus believed that there were infinite number of worlds due to the combinatorial arrangements from atoms, and indeed he turned out to be correct from modern astronomy!

 

There are some caveats we have to be aware of regarding Democritus’ revolutionary thinking of the world. The first one is that, unlike modern empirical science, the theory of atomism was completely based on speculation. It was a rationalist account just like the metaphysical speculations of Parmenides and others. Democritus and his school certainly had no way to observe the existence of atoms, and therefore he could not claim a higher standing for empirical science than the competing theories did. Nevertheless, one should be impressed by his keen insights into things and how he successfully foresaw and inspired later generation of scientists.

 

The second point is that Democritus had a very skeptical attitude of using sense impressions to arrive at true knowledge. That should be surprising for many because many empirically-minded thinkers tended to be materialists for their understanding of the word. Democritus advised his readers against the use of their senses to know something, asserting nothing was true when one acquired them from their sense organs. While I do not think Democritus was completely hostile to observations and empirical methods (he was also an astronomer), he has addressed the possible limitations of our senses to deceive us. It is ironic that his beliefs in atomism would eventually inspire and guide the development of empirical and physical science for the centuries to come.

 

Democritus has given us a very naturalistic view of our world. Are there still any places for the Divine in human existence? What is the direction of human progress? How should we live well according to the atomist doctrines? Well, Democritus had a lot to say about all that!

 

(End of Part 1)

 

by Ed Law

Conatus Classics


Saturday 26 December 2020

Greek Dramatists vs. Filmmakers : Euripides x Peckinpah

 


Euripides and Sam Peckinpah can be considered as the ‘bad boys’ of their respective crafts. Their revolutionary approaches have often exploded and deconstructed the status quo of their artforms. As a contemporary of Sophocles, Euripides has competed with the former tragedian in a number of occasions. Due to the more controversial themes in his plays, Euripides has won less of the competition at City Dionysia, and got a few 3rd places (which unfortunately was the last place of the competition). The people in his era might not get the concerns of Euripides, but the modern audience do: viewing these plays by today’s standard, one will be impressed by how forward-thinking this great tragedian has been in his critique of morality and theodicy, and he has committed to the strongest sense of psychological realism until that point in the history of literature. Euripides’ influences can be found in great playwrights and novelists such as Ibsen, Strindberg and Shaw. Some of his most iconic characters have metamorphosed into the many archetypes we found in cinema and novels of today. Medea, the resourceful woman who committed many acts of revenge and violence in her story, leading to high body-count and culminating in killing her children to strike back at her husband’s infidelity (this plot was likely an Euripides’ innovation), would become the modern ‘Gone Girl’ type of character, which the Japanese word ‘akujo’ (あくじょ悪女) is an appropriate description. Meaning ‘villainess’ or ‘immoral woman’, this type of character often has a perverse sense of charisma in its own right, and that is the type of character where actresses like Isabelle Adjani and Yoshino Kimura are in particular gifted at portraying. If we try to transpose Euripides’ style to the standard of today, works like ‘Medea’ sit comfortably with the style of European Art Cinema. In fact, it should not be surprising that Pier Paolo Pasolini and Lars von Trier have respectively made their own cinema versions of the play, with quite different emphasis.



Sam Peckinpah was a member of the era of New Hollywood cinema in the late 1960s. As an iconoclast of movies, he revolutionized the way of the approaches towards action sequences in cinema. Though his uses of slow-motion shots, fast-cut and analytic editing, with multi-camera captures, action sequences has become more realistic and exciting since Peckinpah. Yet, his idiosyncratic method appeared to come with a cost: the realism he was striving for resulted in spectacularly bloody violence in many of his films, and he was nicknamed ‘Bloody Sam’ for exactly this reason. ‘The Wild Bunch’, widely considered as Peckinpah’s masterpiece, was once seen as the most violent movie in the history of cinema when it first came out in 1969. What is ironic is that the blood-splattering moments account for less than 10 minutes of the 2.5-hour runtime of the film, signifying the intensity and impact of these cinematic images to the audience. Peckinpah was an auteur who specialized in the genre of Revisionist Western – he tried to dissect the true sides of the history of American Frontier. While he had a strong emphasis on history and culture, he was just as concerned about human nature and how that shaped our behavior in the world. Often with a nostalgic and elegiac tone, Peckinpah could also be compared to an ancient Greek poet Theognis, who composed elegiac poems on nature and advocated for a moral existence.

 



An innovation for Euripides was the kind of characters his work focused on. While all the 3 Classical Greek playwrights concentrated on tragic characters, those from Aeschylus and Sophocles tended to be noble and larger-than-life characters. These characters did receive loads of injustice and suffering throughout their ordeals, yet their dispositions and behaviors often served as ideals for the viewers to strive towards. As Sophocles have allegedly noted that his characters were benchmarks of how one ‘ought to be’ in real life, Euripides revolutionized in portraying the experience of the underdogs and rather ordinary people. In particular, given the rather imbalance of power and rights of the both sexes in ancient Greece, Euripides’ tragedies gave voice to the female characters more than the other 2 playwrights did. Notwithstanding, Euripides’ stories were far more realistic and juicier in some aspects. Sex, desire, alienation, madness, aberrations in personality were topics abound in his dramatic universe and they found a lot of resonance to the modern audience. Even when the 3 tragedians were considering the same topic, their emphasis were remarkably different. Take the character of Electra, for example. In ‘Oresteia’, Aeschylus focused on the big picture, chronicled the revenge of Orestes towards her mother. After the death of the mother, the narrative purpose of Electra has diminished. When Sophocles wrote his version of Electra, he focused on creating a psychological portrait of this character, stressing the dispositions and thoughts that led to her reunion with Orestes and the eventual bloodshed. Euripides, in contrast to his predecessors, did not want the audience to believe that the sibling has ‘made their oikos great again’ after the slaughtering of their mother. The tragedian concentrated on the psychological consequences on these two characters after the damage has been done, amplifying the turmoil the sibling had to endure.  

 

The Sophocles / Euripides connection seems to find some parallels with the Kurosawa / Peckinpah connection, and that is the reason why I write this series of articles in the first place. Peckinpah, who admired Kurosawa, has made ‘The Wild Bunch’, which was heavily influenced by ‘Seven Samurai’. While both films may have some narrative similarities, the outlook is in stark contrast, and one can see Peckinpah’s world view was more pessimistic than that of Kurosawa’s (though I would admit this may be an over-generalization in some respect). If Sophocles and Kurosawa demanded their viewers to look carefully at and consider every specific details in the picture, then what Euripides and Peckinpah were doing was to expose all the conflicts and contradictions and thus tore the whole picture apart.   



While Euripides often had strong and intelligent women in his tragedies, and also the tragedies were often named after a female character, it is difficult to consider that as 'feminist' if it puts it into the modern context. I would argue Euripides's approach was similar to the films of Howard Hawks or Kenji Mizoguchi, who appeared to portray women in a strong light, with the independent 'Hawksian women' who often helped or outwitted the male characters in his Film Noir and screwball comedies, or with Mizoguchi, his sympathetic portrayal of women who suffered under the social context. One can argue that it is rather unlikely that a demonstration of feminism was these filmmakers' intention.

 

Yet for Sam Peckinpah, that is a more difficult position! Peckinpah’s cinema has been criticized by many as misogynistic. The female characters, often not important in the narrative sense, were subject to the brutality and violence from men. Classic examples are films like ‘The Wild Bunch’ and ‘The Getaway’, and ‘Straw Dogs’ has reached a level of extreme controversy due to an intense scene of sexual violence towards the female protagonist. This issue regarding Peckinpah’s style is very contentious and the opinions have changed a lot throughout the years. Personally, I do not agree to the viewpoint that Peckinpah was misogynistic. From my observations of all his films, Peckinpah always placed the blame on the male characters. Peckinpah appeared to have a belief in a Hobbesian state of nature, yet he has always demanded humans to be responsible for their actions. If the women in his films were treated unfairly in any sense, that was because the world was flawed as being male-dominated and the characters failed to control their desire and aggression towards others. In fact, for ‘Bring Me The Head of Alfredo Garcia’, a minor yet rather moving scene was when the protagonist and his girlfriend were threatened by a band of violent hooligans, the girl was willing to sacrifice herself to protect the protagonist, eventually raped and murdered by the bad guys (and the protagonist avenged by killing them all). Such a gesture is in no way degradative to women, that affirms women’s courage and gumption. Putting the dramatist and the filmmaker together, one will be baffled by the fact that they were both considered haters of women, with very different reasons: Euripides was considered misogynistic because he frequently portrayed evil and hysterical women; Peckinpah due to his belittling and undermining of the female personality.          



Nevertheless, we should not overlook that Euripides did provide a positive portrayal of female characters in some of his tragedies. He was also a pacifist and advocated for the end of war and maintenance of peace. Work like ‘Trojan Women’ and ‘Orestes’ provided a look into the effects of war on normal people, and he often used his tragedies to comment on the historical context that surrounded him, the fact that Athens was declining at that point and soon entered into military conflicts.

     

Peckinpah situated in a similar kind of era. In fact, Peckinpah has indirectly stated and alluded to the fact that the violence in his film reflected a critique of real life events, especially the Vietnam War. The violence in ‘The Wild Bunch’ was a backlash and wake-up call for the audience, who has become desensitized to the news on the television regarding the ‘progress’ of the Vietnam War. Yet, Peckinpah’s position on war and violence was an ambivalent one. In Straw Dogs, Peckinpah seemed to share a more pessimistic and complex viewpoint – he did not know the answer, and he challenged the viewers to come up with their own answers. On one hand, Peckinpah was critiquing the failure of the pacifying attitudes of the protagonist, David Sumner (Dustin Hoffman). They were bullied by a group of rowdy town men, and Sumner was perceived as a coward and weak by his wife. That went as far when Sumner was tricked and his wife was raped by the men without his knowledge. Surprisingly, the table was turned when in an attempt to save a youngster (who Sumner had no commitment to protect) from the rowdy men, Sumner turned NBK-mode and became so violent that he literally killed every one of these men (bear trap, boiling oil pot, shotgun to blow one of the men’s feet apart, fire poker to a brain matter-splattering end, you name it). The breaking of Sumner’s spectacles signified the breaking point of civilization. Sumner, holder of a professorship of theoretical physics, shifted from a civilized demeanor back to an animalistic, primal state of nature, championing in aggression more than the complex sets of his equations on his blackboard. Peckinpah has maintained consistently that he intended Sumner, who was supposed to be weak and humble, to be the villain of the film. If Peckinpah condemned Sumner due to his choice of violence and his war-like tendencies, then at the same time he was casting doubts on the civilized approach to the conflicts, and that was approaching a sense of nihilism. I am a big fan of ‘Straw Dogs’, yet I can’t make up my mind about the complex issues portrayed in the film. Peckinpah was likely just as undetermined, too.     



Phaedra

What is it when they say that men “love”?

Nurse

That is the sweetest thing, child, and also full of pain.

Phaedra

We only get the second part.

-Euripides, 'Hippolytus'

The conflicts in Euripides’ plays are even more apparent if we consider the heated nomo-physis debate of Classical Athens. Works like ‘Hippolytus’, ‘Orestes’ and ‘Medea’ addressed the implications of this dichotomy. Euripides's meticulous design inferred that, the more the audience wishes to find some order or categorizations in the narrative, the more they will discover the irreconcilable aspects of these conflicting perspectives. While less explored in my previous articles regarding the debate, the distinction of nomos and physis actually followed a more intimate yet sexist view – that nomos was often associated with reason and the male identity, while physis was often associated with emotion and the female identity. The sad fact that some people can still use this assertion to undermine the ability of women in life suggests that humans have not changed much after all. Moreover, ‘physis’ took a more dangerous meaning in a sense relevant to drama: it tended to symbolize the uncontrollable forces of nature, and the chaos that resulted. In ‘Hippolytus’, Hippolytus and Phaedra served as ideas in human form: Hippolytus served as a symbol of ‘nomos’ while Phaedra served as a symbol of desire. The 2 characters had a parallel development in terms of narrative – their flawed character led to their deaths respectively. Hippolytus, a moral and restrained man, could not contain his hubris and felt that his assertion of reason exceeded that of the Divine. Phaedra could not contain her sexual desire and led to conflicted feelings of both love and hate towards Hippolytus. While ‘Medea’ could be considered as a nice portrait of a psychopathic mind, who aced the art of persuasion and rhetoric, Euripides gave Medea complexity by showing the conflict of her reason and passion in a memorable monologue before she murdered her children, showing the bleak impossibility to reconcile both ends. Euripides actually went as far to question if the nomos-physis debate would really contribute to humanity at all – as that seemed the debate to be a key concern for the Sophists of Classical Athens in particular. In ‘The Bacchae’, a god-intoxicated madhouse of drama, Euripides wished to imagine a world when nature and culture were more harmonious and co-existed without any tiffs. Dionysus, a god for wine and also for destruction and chaos, was the protagonist of the play and what took place in the tragedy said more about humans than about gods. We will return to this later, yet at this stage, the statement that ‘one can only win by not playing’ sounds totally reasonable.

 

Peckinpah also imagined, yet his thoughts were nostalgic and elegiac. Peckinpah’s films were also characters in changing times, when they perceived that they were outmoded and could not catch up with the present. Peckinpah’s concerns were realistic and existential, and it was about how the characters found their places in the new world, or how they were destructed by the world. In films like ‘The Wild Bunch’ and ‘Pat Garrett and Billy The Kid’, Peckinpah’s heroes often reminisced the good old days and how fxxked up the universe has become. It was not that they could not accept new things, but the great traditional old ideals – brotherhood, friendship, selflessness - have been undermined by the new values, which were often based on self-interest and corporate greed.  




Euripides's narrative world also questioned the point of reference we took for granted to govern our behavior. Justice, theodicy, moral objectivism were often absent in Euripides’ tragic world. In ‘Herakles’, our hero had a mingled background of both divine and human aspects. While the play appeared to stress Herakles’ status as the son of the Divine, throughout the play he was defined by his human failures and fallacies. Euripides, like his predecessors, appreciated the importance of including supernatural and divine elements in his work, yet they all welcomed both spiritual and secular explanations. Incidents could be attributed to both supernatural causes, or rationalistic causes such as necessity. In the play Herakles has been put into misery by Hera, Zeus’ wife, because the god’s infidelity has led to the birth of Herakles. After proving his manhood by enduring the 12 Labors, everyone might expect a happy ending for our hero. But with Euripides’ master stroke, the hero was again doomed. Euripides’ version of ‘Herakles’ ended with our hero killing his children in a bout of madness, and Hera was behind all this. While the play did not deny Hera’s divine intervention, Euripides provided a moral process to Herakles by having him to feel responsibility for his mistakes. That made Herakles a secular thinker, who did not desire to attribute spiritual factors into explanations. Yet, ‘Herakles’ served as one of Euripides’ greatest critique on traditional conception of religion and gods. When Herakles cried in despair how someone as nasty as Hera could be qualified as a goddess, he was questioning the conception of divine benevolence, and echoed the ‘best of all possible worlds’ theme from theodicy.   

 

Sam Peckinpah’s cinematic world did not place much emphasis on religion or spiritual issues, yet he believed in the transcendence of ideals, when people remembered the past and the great things other people have achieved. At the end of ‘The Wild Bunch’, the 4 old gunmen decided to confront the rouge general and his many associates, in order to save their young friend. Though they were fully aware that they would likely sacrifice their lives by doing this, they decided to hold their beliefs and took a stand on the issue. The climax saw the gunmen killing close of a hundred of the ‘bad guys’, with the help of a Browning automatic throughout the bloodshed, and they all died at the end. The posse, which was assigned to pursue them throughout the film, arrived and investigated their dead bodies. They could not stop feeling a sense of respect to these old men. Though they were enemies, the posse appreciated the values these dead men represented. When the leader of the posse, an old friend of the gunmen, decided to move on, Peckinpah juxtaposed the final images of all the 4 men – they became memories and legends for the future generations.



The conflicts and contradictions inherent in the characters of Euripides led to alienation, and eventually destruction. The alienation experienced by Herakles was not only apparent in his psychological struggle, but that also led to his madness and demise of his children. While Dionysus was a god that signified excitement from art, uncontained desire also led to chaos. The fact that the bundles of drives and properties could not be sorted out in the psyche would result in an identity crisis and a complete breakdown. King Pentheus learnt it the hard way in the tragedy: he literally was torn apart by a number of mad and intoxicated women, the followers of Dionysus, at the end of the play when a party was rolling. The gruesome fate signified the destruction of the human psyche.

 

The characters in Peckinpah’s films also suffered from alienation. For David Sumner in ‘Straw Dogs’, he was trying really hard to be friendly and hospitable. The façade of ‘Mr. Nice Guy’ could not sustain the fact that he was a cold and analytical person, and with the right triggers he became an aggressive killing machine. For ‘Pat Garrett and Billy The Kid’, the two friends became enemies after Pat became a sheriff. Originally sharing similar idealistic beliefs about freedom, Pat feel uneasy because he had to cater the demands of the corporate power, and he knew that soon he would have to face Billy the Kid. Pat lamented the great old days that he has always desired has passed, and he was not the one who once thought himself of. The story ended tragically when Pat finally killed Billy during an ambush. In a symbolic movement by Peckinpah, Pat looked into a mirror and shot the mirror with his pistol, signifying the symbolic death of a conflicted identity.


Concluding Remarks


Euripides and Sam Peckinpah challenged his audience by confronting them with narratives that ends often did not meet. The viewers have to engage with these memorable yet questionable characters, and their views may likely change or evolve through time. Many of the work mentioned in this article deserves a full treatment – and that, will be another story!

 

by Ed Law

Conatus Classics


 

Euripides plays mentioned: Medea, Electra, Herakles, Hippolytus, Trojan Women, Orestes, The Bacchae.

 

Peckinpah films mentioned: The Wild Bunch, Straw Dogs, Pat Garrett and Billy The Kid, The Getaway, Bring me the Head of Alfredo Garcia.

 

Thursday 24 December 2020

天國與地獄



理想國與煉獄之間,是否只是剩下蒼生的掙扎?當每一個人都把離地貼地掛在口中,這種二分法又能否完全解釋世情百態?黑澤明最偉大的作品,每每流露着一種強烈的理想主義,希望可以感染觀眾而去改變世界。但當現實開始出現一種無道德主義的趨勢時,他深深明白到改變風格的必要性。如同很多電影大師一樣,黑澤明知道在最極端的情況下,才能顯現人性善惡最赤裸的一面。今次我談的天國與地獄,就是這樣的一部佳作了!


天國與地獄,一點也不容易寫!因為很多人已經寫過關於這電影的文章,我亦不覺得自己有很多獨特的觀點,所以遲遲沒有下筆。更甚者,黑澤明在電影中提出了很多問題,卻沒有給予答案,可以感受到他對時勢的悲觀。此片沒有一個充滿理想主義的收筆,更沒有一些只懂自我感覺良好的政客所期望的寬心結局。故事的結論,是一個大多數觀眾都不想接受的看法,令人感到很cynical! 儘管如此,天國與地獄流露着深厚的人文主義,在黑澤明電影中算是耀眼的作品。那是絕對值得在此整理一下我的想法的。


故事講述白手興家,真正是成功靠苦幹的鞋業富商權藤(三船敏郎飾),被一位神秘男子擄走自己的兒子,從而勒索他一筆數目頗大的贖金。可惜綁匪作了一個可真不小的錯誤-他竟錯手拐走了權藤部下的兒子進一!現在權藤處於一個道德兩難的局面:基於仁義的考慮,他必須用贖金救回進一,但他現在經濟拮据,必須用這筆錢去幫助自己解決公司內的權力鬥爭。最後他能否權’藤’輕重,找尋到解決問題的至適方案?在户倉警長(仲代達矢飾)所帶領的團隊的偵查下,案子又能否水落石出?而’綁架一代男’的犯案動機又是甚麼?

 

社會上不同的階層發生磨擦,是出於甚麼原因?真的是如某些人所說的'買唔到樓,溝唔到女'?有一些既得利益者,往往覺得自己的成就是靠着自身實力,扭盡六壬地爭取回來,亦會把一些棘手問題的責任推搪給弱勢的人。這些人高舉着'只因你是廢柴'的厥詞,卻忘記了自己的成功其實亦要依仗一定程度的運氣。更加可悲的是,在這些毒舌的背後,往往亦要經歷過一個低潮的時段,才可以靠着不同的因素突圍而出。當看見這些人漠視着貧苦大眾時,不禁要問他們的同理心,是否因為自身經歷的煎熬而變得麻木?

 

有很多人認為,黑澤明在’天國與地獄’所抒發的感受比其前作更為悲觀。這一點是完全合理!因為如果一個電影人要利用其作品去教導人們道德的規條時,那就可見社會是變得很demoralized! 黑澤明觀察到在二戰後的日本,出現了很多社會問題,而且不少人的道德觀開始淪落,連一些基本的觀念也會忽視。受到日本新浪潮和歐洲藝術電影的衝擊,’天國與地獄’亦顯現了頗為獨特的風格。在我看來,縱使此片是由一本美國小說所啟發,其風格更加像歐洲電影:電影明確地分為上下半部,上半部基本上是在權藤的大宅裡面發生,而下半部就集中描述執法人員追輯綁匪的情節。在電影的第一部份,相對局限的場面令電影的氣氛更為緊張。在權藤與綁匪的談判中,每一位持份者都有內心的盤算,每一部棋都可以引致難以預料的結果。在黑澤明擅長的闊銀幕(Tohoscope anamorphic)構圖下,更加突出了事件中不同持份者在事件中所處的位置和情態。警察的仔細監聽,妻子的無助,司機下屬的焦慮和苦苦哀求,股東們看似置身是外但又時時刻刻關注事態的發展,當然還有權藤內心的掙扎。在侷促的空間中,黑澤明沒有像小津安二郎等導演般採用靜態描寫,他用了不少動態的鏡頭,加以一些較為古典的構圖風格(如他經常用的’三角式關係’)。巧妙的是導演故意淡化三船敏郎的角色,使得觀眾不會只把焦點放在他身上,而是集中在整個事件中人與人之間的互動。權藤的家,頓時變成了社會的縮影,每一個人都是持份者!

 

雖然’天國與地獄’並不是武士片,但是亦有探索很多日本武士片的主要命題-人情與義理的衝突 (Giri-Nijo Conflict)。事實上很多同期的武士片,往往偏向支持人情的觀點, 從而去批判武士道和封建思想的守舊。’切腹’,’奪命劍’,’御用金’,’人斬’等六十年代電影,偏重於對個人的關懷多於對武士制度的絕對忠誠。黑澤明在’天國與地獄’,用諷刺的手法突顯了兩個世界的衝突。因為綁匪抓錯了孩子,所以義理的考慮上權藤亦沒有義務去營救他。不錯,這看似是一個很不人道的結論,但這正正就是義理背後的無情。在功利主義的考慮下,權藤應該用那筆錢去為自己救急,以贏得自己公司中的權力鬥爭。因為權藤必須要二選其一,所以他選擇犧牲自己的私利去救進一,是基於人道的關懷,是對人情的一種肯定。或許黑澤明是感到自己的前作忽略了這種觀點,又或者是表現得不夠深刻,所以在此片明顯表態。但黑澤明没有為觀眾引來一個理想化的結果: 權藤作出了抉擇,他亦要付上代價,失去了公司的控制權。在一個功利的社會,有些人不但不會同情他,甚至會覺得他是愚蠢的。但權藤真的能夠算是笨蛋嗎?在片中開始部份,權藤的兒子在和進一玩一個西部槍客的遊戲,權藤言傳身教,提示兒子要懂得機智地躲避,見機行事。可見他思想老練,亦希望兒子能夠學到自己的優點。

 

不過比能力更加重要的,是一個人的道德觀念。權藤肯去幫助進一,是出於他的善心,和他相信的人文精神。當作出了重要的抉擇後,權藤走到城中,看到一間鞋店的鞋匠在工作。他細心地看着店內,仿似想起以前白手興家的事。或者他有經歷過貧苦的時間,有着這種同理心,所以覺得心安理得。這使我想起以前看過一集由Marco Pierre White主持的地獄廚房。在那一集有一位參賽者很不濟。Marco要求參賽者營運一間餐廳,然後看成績去淘汰參賽者。這名參賽者因為廚藝欠佳,導致送餐下單延誤。顧客們都餓着肚子,更弄哭了一位小朋友。但這位參賽者竟然對此視若無睹,繼續在廚房糊里糊塗。最後Marco淘汰了他,亦說出了參賽者失敗的原因:是因為Marco不忍心看見一個小朋友如此挨餓而沒有人理會他。他質疑如果連這樣簡單的關懷也做不到,試問那位參賽者又怎會顧及食物的質素和顧客的感受?  雖然有人會質疑Marco在鏡頭前才這樣說,但一個人能夠如此成功,是必要堅持自己處事的態度,才可以超越自己的標準。說實話,即使那參赛者不是出於真心,只要他肯幫助那孩子,他可能就不會輸掉比賽,亦會得到旁觀者的同情。所以說權藤幫了進一,就算自身利益受損也是心安理得。在社會上,人人利慾薰心,人性就會變得蕩然無存。正如權藤的妻子問他: 如果你連這都不去做,試問你何以為人?

 

最後在户倉警長團隊的努力下,進一獲救,主謀被捕,後來判處死刑。權藤到了監獄, 和敵人來一個face-to-face。雙方隔着屏幕,一個是自由身,另一個則是結局已定。權藤只是想問一個問題:為甚麼大家要互相憎恨?這個是黑澤明透過權藤所問的問題,他看到自己年代的衝突 :冷戰, 政局不隱, 不同思潮和意識形態漸趨激烈的鬥爭,他只是想大家回歸一個人文主義的框架去相處。主謀並没有任何與權藤修補關係的意欲。他首先說自己對心理的分析沒有興趣,不想為自己的所為作出辯護和解說。他說自己犯案的原因,是因為身處在貧寒的地獄中,看到富人的天國感到嫉妒和仇恨。他並沒有說錯,而且黑澤明亦不否定階級鬥爭的存在,但是主謀可以選擇其他方法去改變世界和爭取社會公義,現在他卻是傷害了一個無辜的小孩,是應該要付上責任。說完後,他顯得歇斯底里,看似害怕死亡的來臨。這場討論,最後只是各自表述,並沒有為任何人帶來更深的體會。天國與地獄就像安東尼奧尼的電影一樣,往往沒有一個完滿的結局。電影顯露了問題,提供了思考的空間,卻沒有給予答案。權藤和黑澤明,都想找出人與人之間的共通點,但主謀卻只是找到了難以融合的分離之處。或者,權藤本來就不配知道這個永恒課題的答案。在獄警的引領下,主謀要迎接自己不能逃避的懲罰,只剩下權藤一個人坐在窗外。除了他對人性現實的迷惘外,剩下的,只有那無奈的凝望。


聖誕快樂! 以戲服人在2021年再與大家見面!

           

by Ed Law

以戲服人 Film Analysis